Page 112 - 6688
P. 112

112
              what the words mean. It is an additional conveyed meaning, called an implicature. By stating
              [І], the speaker expects that the listener will be able to work out, on the basis of what is already
              known, the implicature intended in this context.
                     Given  the  opportunity  to  evaluate  the  hamburger,  the  speaker  of  [І]  has  responded
              without an evaluation, thus one implicature is that she has no opinion, either good or bad, to
              express. Depending on other aspects of the context, additional implic-atures (for example, the
              speaker thinks all hamburgers are the same) might be inferred.
              Implicatures are primary examples of more being communicated than is said, but in order for
              them  to  be  interpreted,  some  basic  cooperative  principle  must  first  be  assumed  to  be  in
              operation.

                     Conversational implicature
                     The  basic  assumption  in  conversation  is  that,  unless  otherwise  indicated,  the
              participants are adhering to the cooperative principle and the maxims. In example [7], Dexter
              may appear to be violating the requirements of the quantity maxim.
                     [7]  Charlene: I hope you brought the bread and the cheese.     Dexter: Ah, I brought the
              bread.
                     After  hearing  Dexter's  response  in  [7],  Charlene  has  to  assume  that  Dexter  is
              cooperating and not totally unaware of the quantity maxim. But he didn't mention the cheese. If
              he had brought the cheese, he would say so, because he would be adhering to the-quantity
              maxim. He must intend that she infer that what is not mentioned was not brought. In this case,
              Dexter has conveyed more than he said via a conversational implicature.
                     We can represent the structure of what was said, with b • bread) and c (- cheese) as in
              [8]. Using the symbol +> for an implicature, we can also represent the additional conveyed
              meaning.
              [8]  Charlene: Ь & c?
              Dexter: b     (+>NOTc)
                     It   is important to note that it is speakers who communicate mean-ing via implicatures
              and it is listeners who recognize those com-municated meanings via inference. The inferences
              selected are those which will preserve the assumption of cooperation.

                     Generalized conversational implicatures
                     In the case of example [7], particularly as represented in [8], no special background
              knowledge of the context of utterance is required in order to make the necessary inferences.
              The same  process  of calculating the implicature  will take place if Doobie asks Mary  about
              inviting her friends Bella (= b) and Cathy (= c) to a party, as in [93. ], and gets the reply in [9=b.
              ]. The context is dif-erent from [7], but the general process of identifying the implica-ure is the
              same as in [8].
              [9] a. Doobie: Did you invite Bella and Cathy? (f&c?)
              b. Mary: I invited Bella.    (b+>NOTc)

                     When  no  special  knowledge  is  required  in  the  context  to  calculate  the  additional
              conveyed meaning, as in [7] to [9], it is called a generalized conversational implicature. One
              common example in English involves any phrase with an indefinite article of the type 'a/an X',
              such as 'a garden' and 'a child' as in [ 10]. These phrases are typically interpreted according to
              the generalized conversa-tional implicature that: an X +> not speaker's X.
                 [10] I was sitting in a garden one day. A child looked over the   fence.
   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117