Page 108 - 6688
P. 108

108
                   [2]  a. Mary's dog is cute. (= p)
                          b. Mary has a dog.     (= q)
                          c. p » q
                     Interestingly, when we produce the opposite of the sentence in [2a.] by negating it (=
              NOT p), as in [3а.], we find that the rela-tionship of presupposition doesn't change. That is, the
              same proposition q, repeated as [3 b.], continues to be presupposed by NOT p, as shown in [3
              c.].
                   [3] a. Mary's dog isn't cute. (=NOTp)
                          b.   Mary has a dog. (= q)
                          c.   NOT p »q
                     This property of presupposition is generally described as constancy under negation.
              Basically, it means that the presupposition of a statement will remain constant (i.e. still true)
              even when that     statement is negated. As a further example, consider a situation in which
              you disagree (via a negative, as in [4b.]) with someone who has already made the statement in
              [4a.].
                   [4]  a.  Everybody knows that John is gay.    (=p)
                          b. Everybody doesn't know that John is gay. (=NOT p)
                          c. John is gay.    (=q)
                          d. p »q & NOT p »q
                     Notice that, although both speakers disagree about the validity of p (i. e. the statement
              in [4a.]), they both assume the truth of q (i.e. [4c.]) in making their statements. The proposition
              q, as shown in [4d.], is presupposed by both p and NOT p, remaining constant under negation.

                     Types of presupposition
              In the analysis of how speakers' assumptions are typically expressed, presupposition has been
              associated with the use of a large number of words, phrases, and structures. We shall consider
              these linguistic forms here as indicators of potential presuppositions, which can only become
              actual presuppositions in contexts with speakers.
                   As  already  illustrated  in.  examples  [І]  to  [3],  the  possessive  construction  in  English  is
              associated  with  a presupposition of  ex-istence.  The existential presupposition is  not only
              assumed to be present in possessive constructions (for example, 'your car' » 'you have a car'),
              but more generally in any definite noun phrase. By using any of the expressions in [5], the
              speaker is assumed to be committed to the existence of the entities named.

                   [5] the King of Sweden, the cat, the girl next door,
                                the Counting Crows
                     We shall reconsider the basis of existential presuppositions later, but first we should
              note that  there  was  a  different  type  of presupposition  present in [4]. In [4], the verb  'know'
              occurs  in  a  structure,  'Everybody  knows  that  q',  with  q  as  the  presupposi-tion.  The
              presupposed information following a verb like 'know' can be treated as a fact, and is described
              as a factive presupposition. A number of other verbs, such as 'realize' in [6a.] and 'regret' in
              [6b.], as well as phrases involving 'be' with 'aware' [6c.], 'odd' [6d.], and 'glad' [6e.] have factive
              presuppositions.

                    [6] a. She didn't realize he was ill.             (» He was ill)
                          b. We regret telling him.                 (» We told him)
                          c. I wasn't aware that she was
   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113