Page 114 - 6688
P. 114

114
                     Particularized conversational implicatures
                     Іn  the  preceding  examples,  the  implicatures  have  been  calculated  without  special
              knowledge of any particular context. However, most of the time, our conversations take place
              in very specific con-texts in which locally recognized inferences are assumed. Such inferences
              are  required  to  work  out  the  conveyed  meanings  which  result  from  particularized
              conversational implicatures. As an illustra-on, consider example [І6], where Tom's response
              does not appear on the surface to adhere to relevance. (A simply relevant answer would be
              'Yes' or 'No'. )

                  [І6] Rick: Hey, coming to the wild party tonight?
                         Tom: My parents are visiting.
              In order to make Tom's response relevant, Rick has to draw on some assumed knowledge that
              one college student in this setting expects another to have. Tom will be spending that evening
              with his parents, and time spent with parents is quiet (consequently +> Tom not at party).
                Because they are by far the most common, particularized con-versational implicatures are
              typically just called implicatures. A further example, in which the speaker appears not to adhere
              to (i. e. to 'flout') the maxim of manner, is presented in [17].
                 [17]  Ann: Where are you going with the dog?
                          Sam: TotheV-E-T.
              In the local context of these speakers, the dog is known to re-cognize the word 'vet', and to
              hate  being  taken  there,  so  Sam  pro-duces  a  more  elaborate,  spelled  out  (i.  e.  less  brief)
              version of his message, implicating that he doesn't want the dog to know the answer to the
              question just asked.
              In [І8], Leila has just walked into Mary's office and noticed all the work on her desk. Mary's
              response seems to flout the maxim of relevance.
                    [І8]  Leila: Whoa! Has your boss gone crazy?
                           Mary: Let's go get some coffee.
              In order to preserve the assumption of cooperation, Leila will have to infer some local reason
              (for example, the boss may be nearby) why Mary makes an apparently non-relevant remark.
              The implicature here is essentially that Mary cannot answer the question in that context.
              In addition to these fairly prosaic examples of implicatures, there are other more entertaining
              examples, as in [19] and [20], where the responses initially appear to flout relevance.
                    [19] Bert: Do you like ice-cream?
                           Ernie: Is the Pope Catholic?

                      [2o] Bert: Do vegetarians eat hamburgers?
                             Ernie: Do chickens have lips?
              In [19], Ernie's response does not provide a 'yes' or 'no' answer. Bert must assume that Ernie is
              being cooperative, so he considers Ernie's 'Pope' question and clearly the answer is 'Yes'. So,
              the answer is known, but the nature of Ernie's response also impli-cates that the answer to the
              question  was  'Obviously,  yes!'.  An  additional  conveyed  meaning  in  such  a  case  is  that,
              because the answer was so obvious, the question did not need to be asked. Example [20]
              provides the same type of inferencing with an answer 'Of course not!' as part of the implicature.

                     Properties of conversational implicatures
                     So far, all the implicatures we have considered have been situated within conversation,
              with the inferences being made by people who hear the utterances and attempt to maintain the
   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119