Page 115 - 6688
P. 115

115
              assumption  of  cooperative  interaction.  Because  these  implicatures  are  part  of  what  is
              communicated and not said, speakers can always deny that they intended to communicate
              such meanings. Conversational implicatures are deniable. They can be explicitly denied (or
              alternatively,  reinforced)  in  different  ways.  To  take  a  simple  example,  there  is  a  standard
              implicature associated with stating a number, that the speaker means only that number, as
              shown in [21].
              [21]  You have won five dollars!         (+> ONLY five)
                     As shown in [22], however, it is quite easy for a speaker to sus-pend the implicature (+>
              only)  using  the  expression  'at  least'  [22a.  ],  or  to  cancel  the  implicature  by  adding  further
              informa-tion, often following the expression 'in fact' [22b. ], or to reinforce the implicature with
              additional information, as in [22c. ].
              [22] a.  You've won at least five dollars!
                     b.You've won five dollars, in fact, you've won ten!
                     c.You've won five dollars, that's four more than one!
              .
                     Conventional implicatures
                     In  contrast  to  all  the  conversational  implicatures  discussed  so  far,  conventional
              implicatures are not based on the cooperative prin-ciple or the maxims. They don't have to
              occur in conversation, and they don't depend on special contexts for their interpretation. Not
              unlike lexical presuppositions, conventional implicatures are associated with specific words and
              result in additional conveyed meanings when those words are used. The English conjunction
              'but' is one of these words. The interpretation of any utterance of the type p but q will be based
              on the conjunction p & q plus an implicature of 'contrast' between the information in p and the
              information  in  q.  In  [23],  the  fact  that  'Mary  suggested  black'  (=  p)  is  contrasted,  via  the
              conventional implicature of 'but', with my choosing white (= q).
                  [23] a. Mary suggested black, but I chose white.
                          b. p & q (+>p is in contrast to q)
                     Other  English  words  such  as  'even'  and  'yet'  also  have  conven-tional  implicatures.
              When  'even'  is  included  in  any  sentence  describing  an  event,  there  is  an  implicature  of
              'contrary to ex-pectation'. Thus, in [24] there are two events reported (i. e. John's coming and
              John's helping) with the conventional implicature of 'even' adding a 'contrary to expectation'
              interpretation of those events.
                        [24] a. Even John came to the party.
                                b. He even helped tidy up afterwards.
                     The  conventional  implicature  of  'yet'  is  that  the  present  situation  is  expected  to  be
              different,  or  perhaps  the  opposite,  at  a  later  time.  In  uttering  the  statement  in  [25a.  ],  the
              speaker produces an implicature that she expects the statement 'Dennis is here' (= p} to be
              true later, as indicated in [25b].
                              [25] a. Dennis isn't here yet. (=NOTp)
                                    b. NOT p is true   (+> p expected to be true later)

                     It  may  be  possible  to  treat  the  so-called  different  'meanings'  of  'and'  in  English
              (discussed in Chapter І) as instances of conven-tional implicature in different structures. When
              two statements containing static information are joined by 'and', as in [26a. ], the implicature is
              simply  'in  addition'  or  'plus'.  When  the  two  state-ments  contain  dynamic,  action-related
              information, as in [26b. ], the implicature of 'and' is 'and then' indicating sequence.
                  [26] a. Yesterday, Mary was happy
   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120