Page 80 - 6688
P. 80

80
                                          Classification of Illocutionary Acts

                                      Speech Act Functions and Subfunctions

                    Austin  and  other  philosophers  tried  to  understand  how  an  infinite  number  of
              sentences might reflect a very finite set of functions. They concluded that since the number
              of things we do with words is limited, we ought to be able to assign functions to utterances.
              The  problem  with  assigning  functions  to  sentences  is  that  speaker  intent  and  sentence
              meaning are not always the same, and no utterance is completely context free in terms of
              meaning  or  function.  Nevertheless,  linguists  and  philosophers  (J. Searle,  R. Ohmann,
              K. Bach and H. Harnish, J. McCawley, J. Vendler) have given much attention to differences
              among illocutionary speech acts and proposed various typologies to classify them.
                    Though Austin was the first to delineate illocutionary acts  distinguishing five general
              classes  –  verdicatives,  exercitives,  commissives,  behabitives,  expositives  –  the  most
              prominent  taxonomy  belongs  to  J.R.  Searle.  In  his  article  entitled  “Classification  of
              Illocutionary  acts”  Austin’s  former  student  John  Searle  also  pointed  out  that  there  is  an
              endless number of illocutionary acts. There are statements, assertions, denials, requests,
              commands,  warnings,  promises,  vows,  offers,  apologies,  thanks,  condolences,
              appointments,  namings,  resignations,  etc.  At  the  same  time,  he  observed  that  some
              illocutionary acts are more closely related than others. His classification is the following :

                                                        General functions of speech acts (Searle 1979)

                  Speech act type                Direction of fit          S = speaker; X = situation
              Declarations               words change the world            S causes X
              Representatives            words fit the world               S believes X
              Expressives                words fit the world               S feels X
              Directives                 make the world fit words          S wants X
              Commissives                make the world fit words          S intends X

              1. Representatives are utterances used to describe some state of affairs. They commit the
                speaker  (in  varying  degree)  to  smth’s  being  the  case,  to  the  truth  of  the  expressed
                proposition.  This  class  includes  statements  of  facts,  assertions,  conclusions,
                descriptions,  predictions,  denials,  admissions,  notifications,  etc.  In  using  a
                representative, the speaker makes words fit the world (of belief).
                     Eg.:  a. It’s an interesting book.
                              b. I don’t know Mary Smith.
                              c. It was a nice trip.
              2. Directives are utterances used to try to get the hearer to do smth. They express what
                the speaker wants. The speaker attempts to make the world fit the words. They include
                two subcategories:
                  a)  attempts (of varying degrees) by the speaker to get the hearer to do smth.  They are
                     acts  of  commands,  ordering,  requesting,  suggesting,  insisting,  recommending,
                     warning, advising, etc.
                  b)  questions are used to get the hearer to provide information. This class includes acts
                     of asking, inquiring, etc.
                     Eg.:  a. Close the door.
   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85