Page 98 - 4188
P. 98

96

         the norms of communities, families, and individuals within it. The media
         operate at this societal level, and media effects can be seen at all levels.
         Thus,  the  media  can  affect  us  not  only  one-on-one,  when  we  are
         watching  TV,  for  example,  but  they  also  affect  us  by  affecting  the

         norms,  expectations,  and  patterns  of  behavior  of  our  families  and
         communities. This is another aspect of the media’s subtlety—they can
         affect  us  through  multiple  directions  at  once.  Although  this  makes  it

         likely that everyone will be affected by violent media in some way, it
         also makes it likely that the effects may not be identical for all people.
                 Myth 5. Causality means “necessary and sufficient.”
                 Determining if and when something “causes” something else is a

         problem that has plagued philosophers and scientists for centuries. In the
         social sciences, it is a surprisingly complex problem to solve. For many
         people, however, it has become oversimplified—something is a cause if

         it can be shown to be necessary and/or sufficient as a precursor. This
         position has been used to argue against the effects of media violence.
         Ferguson  (2002),  in  a  response  to  Bushman  and  Anderson’s  (2001)

         meta-analyses of media violence and aggression, stated that: (a) because
         humans  have  always  been  violent,  “violent  media,  then,  are  not  a
         necessary precursor to violent behavior” (p. 446), and (b) because many

         people  who  are  exposed  to  media  violence  never  commit  violent
         behavior,  “violent  media,  then,  are  not  sufficient  to  cause  violent
         behavior”  (p.  446).  This  argument  seems,  on  its  surface,  to  be
         reasonable. Yet this argument actually betrays a grossly oversimplified

         idea of causation. Consider, for example, a rock on the side of a hill.
         Assume that you give the rock a push and it begins rolling down the hill.
         Did you cause the rock to roll down the hill?

                 By  the  argument  laid  out above,  you did not. Rocks have  rolled
         down  hills  for  centuries  without  someone  coming  along  and  pushing
         them.  Therefore  pushing it  is not  necessary.  Furthermore,  many  rocks
         that  are  pushed  do  not  roll  down  hills.  Therefore,  pushing  it  is  not

         sufficient.  Although  pushing  the  rock  was  neither  necessary  nor
         sufficient to make it roll down the hill, that does not mean that it was not
         a cause of the rock’s beginning to roll. Most complex issues of interest

         (such as aggressive behavior) are multicausal. In the present example,
         many other issues interact to determine whether the push you gave to the
         rock caused it to roll down the hill: the force of gravity, the mass of the

         rock,  the  shape  of  the  rock  (round  rocks  require  less  of  a  push  than
         square ones), the friction of the hill surface, the slope of the hill surface,
   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103